I recently learned that MPs have been forbidden from having second jobs, the idea being that a second job would prevent them from focussing sufficiently on their work for the good of the country.
I don't know which dolt thought that one up, but I find it far more likely that MPs with part-time jobs will work better, since they won't be swayed by short-term populism, financial concerns over being granted a paid position as a minister or committee chairman or worries about re-election.
I would even venture to suggest that MPs should be required to have another job, or a fall-back job, confirmed by an employer (but without conflict of interest, such as working in a lobbying company), to ensure their immunity to such concerns.
They would also have more experience of working like the rest of the population, have networks outside of Parliament and the party apparatchiks and have less time for conniving to disenfranchise other voters in political meetings and conferences.
Tuesday, 30 June 2009
Tuesday, 23 June 2009
Disease
I watched an interesting talk today about the possibility of controlling the evolution of infectious diseases.
A few years ago cholera was introduced to Peru, causing an outbreak, and it spread to neighbouring countries such as Ecuador and Chile. But the severities of the outbreaks were very different because these countries have differing qualities of water supply.
The interesting finding was that not only were the severities of the whole outbreaks different, but that the cholera strains had evolved to be milder in places with cleaner water because they needed healthier, more mobile humans in order to be transmitted.
A similar thing could be done for both malaria and HIV; insect-proofing housing in malarial regions would prevent mosquitoes biting severely ill people, and thereby reduce the spread of virulent strains of malaria. A reduction in HIV transmission rate would make HIV evolve to be less aggressive.
For HIV, spread by direct contact, a reduction in contact is always a good thing, and so this theoretical possibility does not suggest a new way to improve HIV care. But in vectorial diseases we have a powerful way to improve the disease.
If microbes in hospitals become resistant to antibiotics they will often be more virulent. If we can identify major routes of transmission and block these preferentially for the most virulent strains (which are easily identified by the worst suffering patients) then this action will not only be directly protective, but preventing some infections, but will introduce a reproductive bias in favour of less aggressive infections.
We need to identify whether transferring patients to specialist wards provides more opportunity to spread infection or reduces it, and whether patients then all share the worst strain on that ward.
Perhaps specialist wards should deliberately take only half the cases, and try to take the worst ones, in order to make the infections evolve to be less problematic, rather than treat one species as all the same.
A few years ago cholera was introduced to Peru, causing an outbreak, and it spread to neighbouring countries such as Ecuador and Chile. But the severities of the outbreaks were very different because these countries have differing qualities of water supply.
The interesting finding was that not only were the severities of the whole outbreaks different, but that the cholera strains had evolved to be milder in places with cleaner water because they needed healthier, more mobile humans in order to be transmitted.
A similar thing could be done for both malaria and HIV; insect-proofing housing in malarial regions would prevent mosquitoes biting severely ill people, and thereby reduce the spread of virulent strains of malaria. A reduction in HIV transmission rate would make HIV evolve to be less aggressive.
For HIV, spread by direct contact, a reduction in contact is always a good thing, and so this theoretical possibility does not suggest a new way to improve HIV care. But in vectorial diseases we have a powerful way to improve the disease.
If microbes in hospitals become resistant to antibiotics they will often be more virulent. If we can identify major routes of transmission and block these preferentially for the most virulent strains (which are easily identified by the worst suffering patients) then this action will not only be directly protective, but preventing some infections, but will introduce a reproductive bias in favour of less aggressive infections.
We need to identify whether transferring patients to specialist wards provides more opportunity to spread infection or reduces it, and whether patients then all share the worst strain on that ward.
Perhaps specialist wards should deliberately take only half the cases, and try to take the worst ones, in order to make the infections evolve to be less problematic, rather than treat one species as all the same.
Wednesday, 17 June 2009
The purpose of marriage
I listened to the second Reith lecture this year
http://www.bbc.co.uk/iplayer/episode/b00l0y01/The_Reith_Lectures_The_Reith_Lectures_2009_Morality_in_Politics/
which is entitled 'Morality in Politics'. Professor Michael Sandel discusses how politics should not attempt neutrality on vexed moral questions, but needs to engage in debate and resolve them.
He also mentions how the attempt to be distanced from moral debate has led us to a flawed tolerance of disagreements, in which we pretend to accept others' opinions whilst finding them fundamentally disagreeable. This chimes nicely with a quotation which I have cherished for some time (and which I took from a games designer called Mark Rosewater, but which is not lessened by its unusual pedigree) and which ends like this:
'When did everyone get so afraid of conflict existing? Conflict is a wonderful thing. It causes resolution.'
We need proper debate about these problems, and that is the one thing that we are not getting. Another news source today mentioned that a few decades ago a politician got about 43 seconds to make a point. A few years ago it was 9 seconds and it is now 6 seconds. The article was attempting to blame computer games and video for shorter attention spans, but whatever the cause, it is clear that we are getting less substantive debate, not more.
Professor Sandel went on to talk about one thing especially: how the state cannot avoid being involved in moral questions. His first example was one in which a disability law made the question of the essential nature of golf a legal question, to be decided by judges, and his second was the subject of homosexual marriages.
States currently all support heterosexual marriages, and Professor Sandel clearly distinguishes between the options of equally supporting all types of marriage, supporting homosexual relationships in a lesser way or under a different name, and not supporting any marriage. As he says, marriage is patently not about procreation, despite many people's protestations.
In his opinion, marriage is about honouring the mutual and exclusive dedication of two people to each other. This honour is conferred not only by name but also through various legal benefits.
His analysis is clear and concise, if a little slowly spoken. It is about other points that we differ. Whereas he believes that the state must support homosexual marriage as an equal with heterosexual marriage, since the individuals have made identical commitments, I think that his examination is enough to show us that the whole institution of marriage is unsound.
Firstly, I see no reason for the state to honour mutual and exclusive dedication at all. Why this is a special form of relationship entirely eludes me; I have no arguments against it, but fail to see justification also. It simply appears ludicrous.
Secondly, I think that legal benefits are better given as support for procreation, if given at all. The mutual dedication is good only because it might (I doubt it) be always better for a child. In this case marriage is flawed because we recognise marriage intrinsically, not parents with children. Thus in some way I actually agree with those who are categorised as right-wing loonies and Christian nutters.
Thirdly, the 'mutual and exclusive' tag can be applied to any number of people. The addition of 'between two people only' is as ludicrous as 'between a man and a woman' if it is only the feelings that we are honouring. This is similar to Professor Sandel's dismissal of the 'simplistic' argument that people should be free to choose their partner. He says that it is not that simple, because of the option of the state not supporting a partner system at all. Rather than choose to remain in a clearly untenable system of thought, as he does, I take this problem as a demonstration that marriage is indeed an arbitrary and unjustifiable legal imposition.
We already know that our states are predicated on the dispensation of as much freedom as possible; it is commonly held that it is good for the state to impose no more on people's choice than is necessary to prevent others within or without society imposing on people's free choice. To support the institution of marriage is therefore beyond the legitimate scope of a government, since it is an arbitrarily chosen good, dependent solely on belief.
The 'right-wingnuts' or whatever they choose to call themselves are quite right. Once marriage is dissociated from child-rearing its value is lost. Where they are wrong is to suppose that it currently is linked to child-rearing and that supporting homosexual marriage will break this link. Until marriage necessarily involves a child then that link does not exist. We have plenty of married couples without children, and plenty who no longer have children.
I'm not even sure that giving any support for child-rearing is a good thing, given the problems of global over-population and people having children just for the benefits. Gregory Clark makes a compelling argument (implicitly in his work) that because child subsidies are proportionally greater for the poor, the poor will have more children, who will have a reduced quality of upbringing the more children the poor have. The rich, who can afford to care for a child better, will feel less incentive.
He also argues that the long-term trickle down of greater fertility in the rich generated the work ethic and culture of personal virtue that started the industrial revolution. While the direct evidence is weak, the possibility is absolutely clear. Although any idea of attempting to control fertility of any group is anathema to modern society, it being claimed that everyone has the right to as many babies as he chooses, this seems silly to me. Soon we will have to indulge in population control anyway.
Furthermore, child subsidies already disproportionately affect the poor. It can be argued just as cogently that we are already therefore favouring fertility in this group, and that changing this system will remove our immoral influence. Of course, this is delving into subjects that could merit a whole discussion of their own.
The last point on this subject (that I have in mind at the moment) is something that Professor Sandel mentioned in his first Reith lecture: that financial incentives replace moral incentives, rather than adding to them. If putting a price on pregnancy (as he mentions in the second lecture) is wrong, then surely a price on child-rearing is wrong. Children should be raised to be moral citizens because it is necessary for society, not because society pays for children and has punishments in place for their immorality.
I would support a centralised child-rearing scheme. If anything is essential to society then future members are. If working members of the public supported both young and old then there might be less of a pensions problem: if there are too few workers to support the aged at some point in the future then it is because those aged did not support enough children when they were working (in a stable society: society with changing life expectancies but not retirement ages, or a society with a shrinking income would suffer anyway).
http://www.bbc.co.uk/iplayer/episode/b00l0y01/The_Reith_Lectures_The_Reith_Lectures_2009_Morality_in_Politics/
which is entitled 'Morality in Politics'. Professor Michael Sandel discusses how politics should not attempt neutrality on vexed moral questions, but needs to engage in debate and resolve them.
He also mentions how the attempt to be distanced from moral debate has led us to a flawed tolerance of disagreements, in which we pretend to accept others' opinions whilst finding them fundamentally disagreeable. This chimes nicely with a quotation which I have cherished for some time (and which I took from a games designer called Mark Rosewater, but which is not lessened by its unusual pedigree) and which ends like this:
'When did everyone get so afraid of conflict existing? Conflict is a wonderful thing. It causes resolution.'
We need proper debate about these problems, and that is the one thing that we are not getting. Another news source today mentioned that a few decades ago a politician got about 43 seconds to make a point. A few years ago it was 9 seconds and it is now 6 seconds. The article was attempting to blame computer games and video for shorter attention spans, but whatever the cause, it is clear that we are getting less substantive debate, not more.
Professor Sandel went on to talk about one thing especially: how the state cannot avoid being involved in moral questions. His first example was one in which a disability law made the question of the essential nature of golf a legal question, to be decided by judges, and his second was the subject of homosexual marriages.
States currently all support heterosexual marriages, and Professor Sandel clearly distinguishes between the options of equally supporting all types of marriage, supporting homosexual relationships in a lesser way or under a different name, and not supporting any marriage. As he says, marriage is patently not about procreation, despite many people's protestations.
In his opinion, marriage is about honouring the mutual and exclusive dedication of two people to each other. This honour is conferred not only by name but also through various legal benefits.
His analysis is clear and concise, if a little slowly spoken. It is about other points that we differ. Whereas he believes that the state must support homosexual marriage as an equal with heterosexual marriage, since the individuals have made identical commitments, I think that his examination is enough to show us that the whole institution of marriage is unsound.
Firstly, I see no reason for the state to honour mutual and exclusive dedication at all. Why this is a special form of relationship entirely eludes me; I have no arguments against it, but fail to see justification also. It simply appears ludicrous.
Secondly, I think that legal benefits are better given as support for procreation, if given at all. The mutual dedication is good only because it might (I doubt it) be always better for a child. In this case marriage is flawed because we recognise marriage intrinsically, not parents with children. Thus in some way I actually agree with those who are categorised as right-wing loonies and Christian nutters.
Thirdly, the 'mutual and exclusive' tag can be applied to any number of people. The addition of 'between two people only' is as ludicrous as 'between a man and a woman' if it is only the feelings that we are honouring. This is similar to Professor Sandel's dismissal of the 'simplistic' argument that people should be free to choose their partner. He says that it is not that simple, because of the option of the state not supporting a partner system at all. Rather than choose to remain in a clearly untenable system of thought, as he does, I take this problem as a demonstration that marriage is indeed an arbitrary and unjustifiable legal imposition.
We already know that our states are predicated on the dispensation of as much freedom as possible; it is commonly held that it is good for the state to impose no more on people's choice than is necessary to prevent others within or without society imposing on people's free choice. To support the institution of marriage is therefore beyond the legitimate scope of a government, since it is an arbitrarily chosen good, dependent solely on belief.
The 'right-wingnuts' or whatever they choose to call themselves are quite right. Once marriage is dissociated from child-rearing its value is lost. Where they are wrong is to suppose that it currently is linked to child-rearing and that supporting homosexual marriage will break this link. Until marriage necessarily involves a child then that link does not exist. We have plenty of married couples without children, and plenty who no longer have children.
I'm not even sure that giving any support for child-rearing is a good thing, given the problems of global over-population and people having children just for the benefits. Gregory Clark makes a compelling argument (implicitly in his work) that because child subsidies are proportionally greater for the poor, the poor will have more children, who will have a reduced quality of upbringing the more children the poor have. The rich, who can afford to care for a child better, will feel less incentive.
He also argues that the long-term trickle down of greater fertility in the rich generated the work ethic and culture of personal virtue that started the industrial revolution. While the direct evidence is weak, the possibility is absolutely clear. Although any idea of attempting to control fertility of any group is anathema to modern society, it being claimed that everyone has the right to as many babies as he chooses, this seems silly to me. Soon we will have to indulge in population control anyway.
Furthermore, child subsidies already disproportionately affect the poor. It can be argued just as cogently that we are already therefore favouring fertility in this group, and that changing this system will remove our immoral influence. Of course, this is delving into subjects that could merit a whole discussion of their own.
The last point on this subject (that I have in mind at the moment) is something that Professor Sandel mentioned in his first Reith lecture: that financial incentives replace moral incentives, rather than adding to them. If putting a price on pregnancy (as he mentions in the second lecture) is wrong, then surely a price on child-rearing is wrong. Children should be raised to be moral citizens because it is necessary for society, not because society pays for children and has punishments in place for their immorality.
I would support a centralised child-rearing scheme. If anything is essential to society then future members are. If working members of the public supported both young and old then there might be less of a pensions problem: if there are too few workers to support the aged at some point in the future then it is because those aged did not support enough children when they were working (in a stable society: society with changing life expectancies but not retirement ages, or a society with a shrinking income would suffer anyway).
Subscribe to:
Comments (Atom)
An ode to niceness
We praise the kind, the soft, the sweet, Who smooth the path of all they meet. A gentle word, a smiling face— Is this the mark of moral...
-
When you want equality with those who are doing well, you might think you have a clear case. There are privileged people out there who h...
-
In the UK we recently suffered the implementation of the 'Online Safety Act'. Labour assumes that it is wildly popular, with a m...
-
We praise the kind, the soft, the sweet, Who smooth the path of all they meet. A gentle word, a smiling face— Is this the mark of moral...