After exploring the ground floor of Rapax castle, including the kitchens, with their unsavoury corpses, the friends wandered down one of the three spiral staircases to the cellar. They could hear brawling ahead and approached cautiously, eventually coming to a room with a bar and numerous kegs of the Rapax tipple, bonecrusher brew. The drunk and intoxicated Rapax seemed to have some sort of disagreement amongst themselves, with some of the senior samurai annoyed at the lack of respect of the drunken soldiers with whom they shared the bar.
"Let's leave them to it." suggested Karen
Sadly, the samurai took the friends to be enemies too, and so the friends mopped up the intoxicated fools quickly, leaving the drunken soldiers to collapse into unconsciousness. Quentin was quickly nosing around the untended bar, and scooped up a few bottles of the powerful spirit.
Down one corridor they found the castle constable in his office, even more drunk then the Rapax in the bar. They couldn't get any conversation out of him except slurring, so they left him there.
The other corridor off the bar led to two dormitories. The first contained a couple of sleepy Rapax, who were not pleased with being awoken. Sadly for them, they weren't in any condition to present a challenge to the friends. Karen displayed her annoyance with being attacked when leaving by dispatching the stupid creatures on her own.
The friends raided the chest in the room and wandered down the corridor to the next dormitory. They searched around for a bit more loot, and Margreet spotted a secret passage in the back of the room, seeing the faint line down the wall that marked the door. Some shoving by Karen and Quentin displaced the heavy stone door and the friends edged into the narrow corridor. It wasn't long, and when Karen and Quentin pushed aside the similar door at the far end they found themselves face to face with a Rapax jail guard, the door opening just behind his desk.
He stretched for his whistle, sitting on the desk, but Quentin lunged forwards to barge him away. Karen started laying into the guard, and Shu Ting emerged quickly to finish the slaughter.
They found themselves inside the gaol, and the cell locks presented quite a challenge to Salva, so they only tried three; one with some blankets in, that might have hidden something, one with a prisoner who was, yet again, drunk. They got nothing from him or his cell. The final one they tried had some new brickwork at the back, and they opened the cell to investigate. Karen punched the wall with her plated fist and the wall moved a little, dust shaking out of the mortar. A few more punches broke the wall down, revealing a passage that they followed.
Saturday, 27 February 2010
Friday, 12 February 2010
Animal rights
'Derek: Try me. I would honestly like to know what it is that makes it ok to eat cows but not humans. But if you aren't articulate enough to explain it then don't bother.
CG: How can I explain this to Derek?'
Cows are incapable of giving consent to the rights and responsibilities of society. They therefore do not get the same rights as those who do.
Longer answer:
Firstly, no, there are some humans who cannot give consent. Typically, they already have or might in the future (disabled people and babies respectively). You could build an argument about that.
If he queries why consent is important, you can similarly ask why the ability to suffer is important, that probably being the basis of his views. Both are arbitrarily chosen. He can use the argument to query your opinions, but his opinions are just as vulnerable. The conclusion therefore is certainly not to avoid eating cows.
Next up, he'll ask why rights and responsibilities go together: why a cow must consent to the responsibilities of society before it can have rights. At this stage we have to admit that it could be granted legal protections by society without consenting to them, but we will also point out that there is no over-riding moral justification for such protections.
Rights and responsibilities go together because they are the inverse of one another. The right not to be murdered is simply everyone else having a responsibility not to murder you.
At this stage we are getting into quite fundamental ideas about whether rights are fundamental and universal, which they quite clearly are not.
You could say that it is incredible that he can imagine an obligation governing a person who has not consented to it. That's a perfect description of a fundamental right: if a cow has a fundamental right not to be eaten, then this is the same as an obligation on me not to eat it, despite me never agreeing to such a thing.
You could also ask him whether predators in the wild are criminals. He will probably come up with some foolish notion that 'they know no better'. We can ignore his assumption of superiority, and bring up an interesting point of established law:
ignorance of the law is not an excuse for breaking it.
We can also wonder why being able to think suddenly gives us obligations, without even consenting.
Let us quote a wise old man (Albus Dumbledore): 'it is the choices we make that truly determine who we are'.
Thinking is not a choice. Consent is the choice. Consent is the action. If I am a criminal simply by virtue of my ability to think then I have been condemned for something that I cannot control.
That is the morality of fundamental rights. They grant rights on the basis of characteristics that are beyond the control of the being that is being given those rights, and are also beyond the control of the beings that must respect those rights. Fundamental rights therefore impose responsibilities, based solely on the belief of the person ascribing those fundamental rights. If we're going to choose arbitrary characteristics, we could just as easily choose humanity as the characteristic that determines whether a being gets rights or not.
On the other hand, if we believe that such an imposition is impossible to justify, the only way that responsibilities can govern a being is if that being has consented to them. This makes much more sense, since the consequences (being wrong or right in a moral sense) are now dependent on our actions, not on arbitrary characteristics such as being able to think, and we typically view moral judgement as being a way of judging actions.
CG: How can I explain this to Derek?'
Cows are incapable of giving consent to the rights and responsibilities of society. They therefore do not get the same rights as those who do.
Longer answer:
Firstly, no, there are some humans who cannot give consent. Typically, they already have or might in the future (disabled people and babies respectively). You could build an argument about that.
If he queries why consent is important, you can similarly ask why the ability to suffer is important, that probably being the basis of his views. Both are arbitrarily chosen. He can use the argument to query your opinions, but his opinions are just as vulnerable. The conclusion therefore is certainly not to avoid eating cows.
Next up, he'll ask why rights and responsibilities go together: why a cow must consent to the responsibilities of society before it can have rights. At this stage we have to admit that it could be granted legal protections by society without consenting to them, but we will also point out that there is no over-riding moral justification for such protections.
Rights and responsibilities go together because they are the inverse of one another. The right not to be murdered is simply everyone else having a responsibility not to murder you.
At this stage we are getting into quite fundamental ideas about whether rights are fundamental and universal, which they quite clearly are not.
You could say that it is incredible that he can imagine an obligation governing a person who has not consented to it. That's a perfect description of a fundamental right: if a cow has a fundamental right not to be eaten, then this is the same as an obligation on me not to eat it, despite me never agreeing to such a thing.
You could also ask him whether predators in the wild are criminals. He will probably come up with some foolish notion that 'they know no better'. We can ignore his assumption of superiority, and bring up an interesting point of established law:
ignorance of the law is not an excuse for breaking it.
We can also wonder why being able to think suddenly gives us obligations, without even consenting.
Let us quote a wise old man (Albus Dumbledore): 'it is the choices we make that truly determine who we are'.
Thinking is not a choice. Consent is the choice. Consent is the action. If I am a criminal simply by virtue of my ability to think then I have been condemned for something that I cannot control.
That is the morality of fundamental rights. They grant rights on the basis of characteristics that are beyond the control of the being that is being given those rights, and are also beyond the control of the beings that must respect those rights. Fundamental rights therefore impose responsibilities, based solely on the belief of the person ascribing those fundamental rights. If we're going to choose arbitrary characteristics, we could just as easily choose humanity as the characteristic that determines whether a being gets rights or not.
On the other hand, if we believe that such an imposition is impossible to justify, the only way that responsibilities can govern a being is if that being has consented to them. This makes much more sense, since the consequences (being wrong or right in a moral sense) are now dependent on our actions, not on arbitrary characteristics such as being able to think, and we typically view moral judgement as being a way of judging actions.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)
Female entitlement
There is a segment of society that claims to believe in equality and fairness; and yet refuses to examine the privileges of one half of ...
-
When you want equality with those who are doing well, you might think you have a clear case. There are privileged people out there who h...
-
I was listening to a podcast about fraud in academia which resonated with me. I left academia behind, not because of any fraud that I ha...
-
Our understanding of what politics in a democracy should be like is sadly lacking. In fact, the yawning chasm between how we act and how...