Wednesday, 19 July 2017

Inequality



Inequality regularly makes the news; when we see reports that inequality is rising, there’s no need to complain too much that it doesn’t reflect everything in an economy. Inequality as measured in a Gini coefficient is one important thing to consider, and if inequality increases, people should wonder if we can stop that.
               But the reverse isn’t true. When our inequality measure shows inequality decreasing, it doesn’t necessarily mean that all is well with the economy, and that’s my subject for today.
               First of all, let’s take a look at income inequality as it was in the UK for income taxpayers, just to get an idea of what this sort of information looks like.

Graph 1

               This graph shows the total income subject to tax for someone at each percentage point for income in the population, for those with taxable income only (for more information about the data, see HMRC’s Survey of Personal Incomes 2013-14). So, for example, the person with the middle income, at 50% of the population, earned £20,020 after tax. The person at the top (the 99th percentile) earned £103,427 in the year.
               The next bit is important, but a bit involved. The way to represent inequality calculations is by summing the incomes and plotting the cumulative income for everyone under that percentile. The graph looks like the lower plot on graph 2. That curve shows the accumulated income of a segment of a population. For example, the bottom 20% of taxpayers earned 9.8% of income. The bottom 90% earned about 78% of income.
               On the same scale I’ve overlaid a plot of complete equality, in which everyone earns the same amount. As everyone earns the same amount, the cumulative score increases linearly as we add extra people to our total, and we get a straight line. Inequality is calculated by comparing the area between the two lines to the size of the whole triangle underneath the straight line (i.e the area between the plot of perfect equality and the axes). That triangle represents what this measure calls perfect inequality: if one person had all the income, the cumulative total would remain 0 right until the very end, when it would suddenly leap to 100% of all income. So what we’re doing is seeing how far between complete equality and inequality we are; we measure the proportion of complete inequality we see in the country.
Graph 2
               I do think it’s important to point out that of us regard perfect inequality as a lot less troublesome than perfect equality. I, for one, wouldn’t like to earn exactly the same as everyone else; it would be a pay cut, I’d feel unrewarded for my expertise, and I’d have no incentive to work harder, learn or improve. But I would hugely prefer that to earning nothing at all while someone else got all the country’s income. So although inequality is measured on a scale of 0 (perfectly equal) to 1 (perfectly unequal), we should skew our expected range to be closer to 0 than to 1. But in the end, measures like this are about detecting change; we use them to compare different countries and change within a country.
That means that we’re looking for improvement that represents improving lives, and as soon as we start using specific measures to analyze general concepts such as wellbeing and inequality, we need to be aware that no individual measure will incorporate everything that we understand in the general term. We need a range of measures, and we need to understand how and why they change, rather than just believing that a change in the number is either good or bad. In other areas, such as targets within a company or the NHS, using a measure can change behavior so that the measure improves but overall circumstances don’t.
So why and how can inequality change? We’ve already considered two extremes: perfect equality and perfect inequality. But what about another scenario just to illustrate other odd possibilities? How about graph 3? Here I’ve given half the population no income and the remaining half share the income equally. This gives us an inequality coefficient of 0.5. If we were thinking simplistically, we’d assume that this was a tolerable situation. After all, we don’t like 0, and we don’t like 1; we want something that’s a pleasing balance between the two. And 0.5 is balanced between 0 and 1! Yet this distribution seems very unfair.
Graph 3
               Graph 3 therefore nicely demonstrates that inequality as a simple number doesn’t mean much. We have to assume that the rough shape of the Lorenz curve remains the same and that a change in inequality represents just a slight shift one way or another. Drastic leaps and jumps in which income varies hugely between percentiles of the population can distort the measure. And graph 3 is based on a very drastic leap in income at the 50th percentile, as shown in graph 4, which plots the underlying incomes used for the cumulative totals of graph 3.

Graph 4
               I hope this establishes perhaps the most important point I want to make here: that fairness is not the same as inequality, or any other economic measure. Economists measure whole-population effects, and a whole-population measure typically can’t detect large leaps and dips: they’re ‘averaging’ across everyone. The UK had a Gini coefficient (the measure usually used, and which I’m describing here) of 0.356 in 2014. That’s not so far off the 0.5 of graphs 3 and 4. I could probably create a distribution very much like graph 4 which had a Gini coefficient of 0.36.
               But what I have instead are some slight variations on the real income distribution of graph 1.

Graph 5
               Graph 5 shows something very similar to graph 1. Total income is roughly equivalent, but the main difference is the top end (note the scale on the y axis). Graph 5 shows a similar gradual increase in income across the population, but without the very big increases amongst the richest. Graph 6 shows the cumulative distribution for the same data.
Graph 6
We can see that although graph 5 isn’t a flat line with everyone earning the same, the Lorenz curve (the name economists give to this cumulative income graph) is extremely close to ‘perfect equality’, and the Gini coefficient very close to 0. The same would apply with a doubled gradient on the slope of graph 5; graph 7 shows the Lorenz curve if I double the changes from the midpoint. The inequality coefficient for incomes that vary linearly from £4,000 to £44,000 (instead of £14,000 to £34000) is still very close to 1.
Graph 7
This shows us another feature of inequality measures: they’re insensitive to linear changes. As long as the relationship is linear we need a massive change to make much difference. For incomes to look even moderately unequal we need to leave the linear relationship behind and try exponential relationships.
It’s very important to point out here that I doubled the difference of a percentile’s income from the midpoint. If I had doubled everyone’s income then inequality wouldn’t have changed, because the measures have been deliberately designed to detect proportional differences, not absolute differences. In graph 5 the highest earners earn £20,000 p.a. more than the lowest, which is about 2.5 times their salary. If we double everything, the lowest earners would earn £28k, the highest earners £68k and the difference would be £40,000. Inequality would be exactly the same, even though the highest earners would now earn £40,000 more than the lowest earners, not £20,000.
If I were to keep the same slope, and keep the earnings difference between top and bottom at £20k, but still double total income (i.e. give everyone an extra £24k each) then inequality would drop.
This is important, because earnings aren’t the only measure of quality of life. We also need to understand what people can buy with their earnings. There’s a minimum level of expenditure that’s required in order to live in the UK (yes, I know that accommodation costs in particular vary a lot, but for the moment let’s simplify and assume that the minimum applies across the whole country evenly).
We know that the minimum wage doesn’t provide the minimum level of expenditure because there are long-running campaigns about the ‘living wage’, which is higher than the minimum wage. But just for this argument, I’ll set it at the lowest percentile of income in graph 5.
If we assume that the bare necessities cost this much, then the lowest earners have absolutely no spare spending money for luxuries, mishaps, presents and personal expenditure. The highest earners have £20k spare for such things; more than the low earners’ entire income. Our measure of inequality suggests that this distribution is close to perfect equality, but as soon as we introduce a minimum necessary level of expenditure, we change our understanding of people’s lives. Some people can afford no luxury or deviation from the absolute minimum, whilst others have a wide choice. The ability to choose interests or activities to pursue is an essential part of human flourishing (and, incidentally, an assumption of free market economics). People who are trapped in only one set of choices do not feel happy or wealthy, no matter what the Gini coefficient might say.
Finally, let’s look at something more realistic.
Graph 8
Graph 8 shows us something a lot closer to the real distribution we saw in graph 1, but accentuated a bit. As we have learned, the gradual increase across much of the population in graph 1 makes little difference to inequality measures, so I’ve left it flat. Now we’re looking at the tails of the population. Yet again, total income is roughly similar.
If we plot the Lorenz curve for this, we see that the tails do matter; that big leap at the end drives a narrow wedge between our line and ‘perfect equality’. But overall the equality coefficient is still very low. Most of the population (between the 4th and 97th percentiles, or 95% of the population) is absolutely equal, and that’s what the measure detects. Those other 5% drag the number away from perfect equality, up to about 0.3.Just by looking at the measure of equality, we might say that this society is slightly more equal than our own, and therefore a bit of an advance. Yet it’s a combination of perfect equality, which we don’t like, and perfect inequality, which we hate.
Graph 9

Inequality isn’t the same as fairness. For humans, those cases at the end matter. If I told you that we could all live happily if we just sacrificed 3 in 100 of the population, most people would say that human sacrifice isn’t an option. It’s not right, and it’s not fair. But economic measures don’t account for this. A few people here or there don’t change the bulk figures, but they matter enormously for our perceptions of society. I haven’t even touched on how enormous wealth differences distort power relations, or how greater ability to spend on luxuries ‘distorts’ the market for goods /luxuries away from what the population might want. Those are topics for you to ponder, bearing in mind that the difference between people’s self-directed expenditure is proportionally vastly greater than their plain incomes, due to our threshold effect.
Our society might be slightly more equal, according to the Gini coefficient, but we need to understand the distribution changes underlying this before we judge whether this is good or not. Our society can easily have become more equal and yet also become much less fair. If the 1% (or 0.01%) at the top earn millions of pounds and do not deserve it (and yes, judging what a person deserves could occupy many other essays) then we are right to complain about economic injustice even if ‘inequality’, as measured by this one economic measure, is lower. Justice and social equality is about whether a person’s situation is fair when compared to any other person in society, not most others, all others, or the average.

Female entitlement

  There is a segment of society that claims to believe in equality and fairness; and yet refuses to examine the privileges of one half of ...